T-to-C movement and (Un)Ambiguity of Uncontracted Negative Interrogatives
© 2022 KASELL All rights reserved
This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons License, which permits unrestricted non-commercial use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Abstract
There are two types of negative interrogatives: contracted negative interrogatives and uncontracted negative interrogatives. There is a consensus that the former type permits a sentential negation reading only. However, there is speaker variation about the latter type. Some speakers permit both a sentential negation reading and a constituent negation reading, whereas some others reject the possibility that it can give a sentential negation reading. Sentential negation and constituent negation are usually in complementary distribution: that is, it is hard to find a construction in which the negative word not can be used as either sentential negation or constituent negation. However, this paper claims that (i) T-movement can give rise to structural ambiguity between a sentential negation reading and a constituent negation reading, (ii) the uncontracted negative interrogative is a case in point, and (iii) the speaker variation about the uncontracted negative interrogative follows from a Gricean Maxim—the Maxim of Manner.
Keywords:
T-to-C movement, contracted negative interrogatives, uncontracted negative interrogatives, sentential negation, constituent negationAcknowledgments
This work was supported by the research fund (2022) of Hankuk University of Foreign Studies. I am thankful to two anonymous reviewers of Korean Journal of English Language and Linguistics for their helpful comments and suggests. Usual disclaimers apply.
References
- Abels, Klaus. 2004. Right node raising: Ellipsis or ATB movement? In Keir Moulton and Matthew Wolf, eds., NELS 34, 45–60. Amherst: University of Massachusetts, Graduate Linguistic Student Association.
- Abusch, Dorit. 1994. The scope of indefinites. Natural Language Semantics 2, 83–136. [https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01250400]
- Beghelli, Filippo. 1995. The Phrase Structure of Quantifier Scope. Dissertation, University of California, Los Angeles.
- Bresnan, Joan. 2001. Explaining morphosyntactic competition. In M. Baltin and C. Collins, eds., Handbook of Contemporary Syntactic Theory, 11–44. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers.
- Bošković, Željco. 2007. On the locality and motivation of Move and Agree: An even more minimal theory. Linguistic Inquiry 38, 589–644. [https://doi.org/10.1162/ling.2007.38.4.589]
- Bošković, Željco. 2011. Last resort with Move and Agree in derivations and representations. In C. Boeckx, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Linguistic Minimalism, 327–353. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199549368.013.0015]
- Bjorkman, Bronwyn and Hedde Zeijlstra. 2019. Checking up on ϕ-Agree. Linguistic Inquiry 50, 527–569. [https://doi.org/10.1162/ling_a_00319]
- Cecchetto, Carlo. 2004. Explaining the locality conditions of QR: Consequences for the theory of phases. Natural Language Semantics 12(4), 345–397. [https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-004-1189-x]
- Chomsky, Noam. 1986. Barriers. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Chomsky, Noam. 2000. Minimalist inquiries: The framework. In Roger Martin, David Michaels and Juan Uriagereka, eds., Step by Step: Essays on Minimalist Syntax in Honor of Howard Lasnik, 89–155. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Chomsky, Noam. 2001. Derivation by phase. In Michael Kenstowicz, ed., Ken Hale: A Life in Language, 1–52. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Chomsky, Noam. 2013. Problems of projection. Lingua 130, 33-49. [https://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2012.12.003]
- Embick, David and Rolf Noyer. 2001. Movement operations after syntax. Linguistic Inquiry 32, 555–595. [https://doi.org/10.1162/002438901753373005]
- Farkas, Donka. 1981. Quantifier scope and syntactic islands. In Roberta A. Hendrick, Carrie S. Masek and Mary Frances Miller, eds., Papers from the 17th Regional Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society, 59–66. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago, Chicago Linguistic Society.
- Farkas, Donka F. and Anastasia Giannakidou. 1996. How clause-bounded is the scope of universals? In Teresa Galloway and Justin Spence, eds., Proceedings from Semantic and Linguistic Theory VI: 35–52. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University, CLC Publications. [https://doi.org/10.3765/salt.v6i0.2764]
- Fox, Danny. 2000. Economy and Semantic Interpretation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Frampton, John. 2001. The amn’t gap, ineffability, and anomalous aren’t: Against morphosyntactic competition. In M. Andronis, C. Ball, H. Elston and S. Neuvel, eds., Papers from the 37th Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society. Vol. 1: 399-412. Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society.
- Grice, Paul. 1975. Logic and conversation. In P. Cole and J. Morgan, eds., Syntax and Semantics 3, 41–58. New York: Academic Press.
- Grosz, Patrick Georg. 2015. Movement and agreement in right‐node‐raising constructions. Syntax 18, 1–38. [https://doi.org/10.1111/synt.12024]
- Ha, Seungwan. 2008. Ellipsis, Right Node Raising, and Across-the-board Constructions. Boston, MA: Boston University dissertation. [https://doi.org/10.3765/bls.v34i1.3562]
- Haegeman, Liliane. 1995. The Syntax of Negation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511519727]
- Haegeman, Liliane. 2000a. Inversion, non-adjacent-inversion, and adjuncts in CP. Transactions of the Philological Society 98, 121–160. [https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-968X.00060]
- Haegeman, Liliane. 2000b. Negative preposing, negative inversion, and the split CP. In L. Horn and Y. Kato, eds., Negation and Polarity, 21–61. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Haegeman, Liliane and Raffaella Zanuttini. 1991. Negative heads and neg criterion. The Linguistic Review 8, 233–251. [https://doi.org/10.1515/tlir.1991.8.2-4.233]
- Iatridou, Sabine and Hedde Zeijlstra. 2013. Negation, polarity, and deontic modals. Linguistic Inquiry 44, 529–568. [https://doi.org/10.1162/LING_a_00138]
- Kim, Kwang-sup. 2022. On T-movement. Lingua 274. [https://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2022.103354]
- May, Robert. 1985. Logical Form. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Matushansky, Ora. 2006. Head movement in linguistic theory. Linguistic Inquiry 37, 69–109. [https://doi.org/10.1162/002438906775321184]
- Potsdam, Eric. 1998. Syntactic Issues in the English Imperative. New York: Garland Publishing.
- Rizzi, Luigi. 1996. Residual verb second and the wh-criterion. In A. Belletti and L. Rizzi, eds., Parameters and Functional Heads, 63–90. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Roberts, Ian. 1998. Have/Be Raising: Move F and procrastinate. Linguistic Inquiry 29, 113–125. [https://doi.org/10.1162/002438998553671]
- Sabbagh, Joseph. 2007. Ordering and linearizing rightward movement. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 25, 349–401. [https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-006-9011-8]
- Sabbagh, Joseph. 2008. Right node raising and extraction in Tagalog. Linguistic Inquiry 39, 501–511. [https://doi.org/10.1162/ling.2008.39.3.502]
- Wilder, Chris. 1999. Right node raising and the LCA. In Sonya Bird, Andrew Carnie, Jason D. Haugen and Peter Norquest, eds., Proceedings of the 18th West Coast Conference in Formal Linguistics, 586-598. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.
- Wurmbrand, Susi. 2018. The cost of raising quantifiers. Glossa: A Journal of General Linguistics 3(1), 19. [https://doi.org/10.5334/gjgl.329]
- Zeijlstra, Hedde. 2012. There is only one way to agree. The Linguistic Review 29, 491–539. [https://doi.org/10.1515/tlr-2012-0017]